Natural Law and Anarcho-Capitalism
June 6, 2020
The purpose of this paper is to give an analysis and explication of the notion of a natural order of human affairs, which is logically independent of any metaphysical or theological system.– Natural Law: A Logical Analysis, Frank van Dun
In this paper, Frank van Dun (FvD) offers
an examination of Rothbardian anarcho-capitalism and its presupposition
of a natural order – based on natural law and natural rights.
In short, anarcho-capitalism, in its Rothbardian form, stands or falls with its suppositionthat there is a natural order – a natural law – of the human world and that each human person has a place in that order that is delimited by his or her natural rights.
It is important that van Dun clarifies that
he is dealing with a Rothbardian order, as others base their
anarcho-capitalism or libertarianism on foundations other than natural
law. Rothbard’s version is not driven by views on efficiency, but on
views of human beings as human beings.
Safe Brass BBQ Grill C...
Buy New $12.23
(as of 03:21 EDT - Details)
It is important, therefore to examine just
what is meant by natural law – at least as van Dun sees it. As he
notes, “‘Natural law’ is a controversial concept.” One reason it is
controversial is that it is often connected to the metaphysical, or
otherwise connected to a particular theology. While one cannot escape
Aquinas when discussing natural law, this certainly does not make it a
Catholic convention – or invention.
However, the fact that some theories of natural law are metaphysical or theological does not mean that natural law is something metaphysical or theological. A theory of mice and men can be metaphysical but the metaphysics is in the theory, not in the mice and not in the men.
FvD then dives into a very important point –
one that I have often made, yet still find misunderstood. Natural law
legal theory and natural law ethical theory need not be identical. Such
thinking results in an unnecessary either / or situation:
…either all natural laws are mere moral admonitions or all of them are legally enforceable requirements. That ambiguity has plagued the interpretation of natural law theories ever since Thomas Aquinas identified natural law and reason.
Natural law: either suggestions for ethical
behavior or a system by which to implement a theocracy. But neither
extreme is necessary, and in any case not at all intended by
Aquinas. Forgive the very long cite, but this is a tremendously
important point:
…Thomas clearly distinguished between mere sins (that merit disapproval and repentance) and injustices (that merit ‘action in justice’ and redress). He also distinguished between vices of the sort no virtuous man would engage in and vices that threaten the existence of ‘society’ (not this or that particular society but ‘human society’ as a general form of conviviality or symbiosis): murder, arson, theft, fraud, robbery, assault and other crimes against persons and property. (Summa Theologica, IaIIae, question 96, art.2 (concl). Only with respect to injustice and especially crime can the coercive power of ‘human law’ intervene. In short, while all virtues are necessarily lawful (sanctioned by the rational appreciation of their agreement with divine providence), and all vices are consequently unlawful, only a few vices of a particular sort should be made illegal. ‘Legislating morality’ was not on Thomas’ agenda.
FvD uses the terms “unlawful” and “illegal”
to make the distinction. Unlawful being a violation of natural law;
illegal being a violation that gets you thrown in prison (or justifies
violence in response).
Marshmallow Roasting S...
Buy New $16.99
(as of 03:21 EDT - Details)
This is consistent with my point that the
non-aggression principle fits quite well as a theory of punishment, but
not as a theory of ethics. Violations of the natural law that are also
aggressions against person or property are subject to the “coercive
power of human law.” Non-aggressive violations of the natural law are
not, in my opinion, subject to this same coercive power.
I will leave aside, as it is rough around
the edges and will be dictated by local custom as much as any other
factor, the specific application of the word “aggression.” I don’t
think the edges of this term are identifiable by evermore purifying
attempts at applying libertarian theory. Human beings don’t work that
way. Different societies will figure this out in a way that works for
them.
FvD next looks at a comparison of natural
law and artificial law. Whether in physics, biology, or chemistry,
science attempts to identify the natural order of things. It is no
different when working to identify the natural order of persons. This
order exists, waiting to be discovered, based on the characteristics of
human beings as human beings.
This as opposed to artificial law: “An
artificial law is an order of artificial things. Here we shall consider
it only as an order of artificial persons.” FvD offers as an example,
the artificial person known as a “citizen.” States and corporations
also qualify. These are defined by the relevant artificial law.
To find out about natural persons, go live among them; to find out about citizens, consult a lawyer!
A breakdown in artificial law happens when
people refuse to play by the rules. This could be because they refuse
to do so (including for reasons that the rules violate natural law) or
when the rules are overly complex and ever-changing. A breakdown of
natural law happens when people do not heed the distinction of one
person from another. (Egalitarianism in all its forms, run amok.)
What of any obligation for a person to
respect the natural law? This, van Dun suggests, is an open question
requiring serious thought:
What a natural person can do does not translate into what he may do. What such a person ought to do does not translate into what he must do.
How I see this: A natural person can punch someone in the nose for no good reason; it does not follow that he may do this. A natural person ought not live in a drunken stupor; yet this says nothing about what he must do regarding the consumption of alcohol.
OPOLAR 10000mAh 8-Inch...
Buy New $39.99
(as of 03:21 EDT - Details)
Such an is-ought question is not an issue
at all for artificial persons and artificial law. Here, the law is
whatever the law is, and the person is whatever the law makes him to
be. This is positivism, and it is clear why positivism is anathema to
anarcho-capitalists – and many libertarians. Positivism ignores, and
even denies, the idea of natural law.
Conclusion
In this paper, van Dun is not attempting to
justify natural law, only to examine it and its relationship to
anarcho-capitalism. He concludes:
Anarcho-capitalism rests on the notion of natural law as an order of natural persons rather than a binding set of rules or commands. As a normative theory, it holds not only that we have good reasons to respect the natural order but also that we have no right not to respect it.
Building liberty on any other foundation is
flawed; it is not sustainable. Only this foundation of natural law
takes human beings as they are, not as someone wishes them to be.
Reprinted with permission from Bionic Mosquito.
No comments:
Post a Comment